Saturday, March 06, 2010

Survey of Utility Theory?

1.0 Introduction
I think utility theory has a canonical textbook presentation. Many variations seem to exist. In some, the additional structure is imposed on the (commodity?) space over which agents choose. In others, more basic assumptions are made from which preferences can be derived under certain special cases.

I'd like to know if there are any surveys to read over these variations. I'm not insisting on something critical. And, given the dryness of the subject matter, I might not put such a survey on top of my queue. As can be seen below, I'm not sure of the field that would be demarcated by such a surveys. But literature surveys, in some sense, construct their object.

2.0 Textbook Treatment
Consider a space of n commodities. Each element of the space is a vector x = (x1, x2, ..., xn). Under the usual interpretation, xi is the quantity of the ith commodity.

An agent is modeled as having a preference relation, ≤, over the space of commodities. A typical question is what assumptions must hold for a utility function to exist. A utility function u(x) exists if, for all x and y in the space of commodities:
xy if and only if u(x) ≤ u(y)

Typically, the preference relation is taken to be a total order, that is, complete, reflexive, and transitive. A preference relation is complete if, for all x and y in the space of commodities,
xy or yx
A preference relation is reflexive if, for all x in the space of commodities
xx
A preference relation is transitive if, for all x, y, and z in the space of commodities,
if xy and yz then xz

If the quantities of commodities fall along a continuum, a preference relation being a total order is not sufficient for a utility function to exist. Lexicographic preferences are an example of a preference relation for which a utility function does not exist. A continuity assumption rules out this case. This assumption is that for all x in the space of commodities, the sets {y | yx} and {z | xz} of commodities not preferred to x and commodities x is not preferred to, respectively, are closed.

Theorem: If a preference relation is a total order and is continuous in the above sense, then a utility function exists.

The utility function is only defined up to a monotonically increasing transformation. In other words, utility is ordinal. Typical exercises are to show certain properties of utility functions, such as ratios of marginal utilities (du/dxi)/(du/dxj), are invariant over the set of such transformations.

3.0 Probability
Von Neumann and Morgenstern generalized the commodity space to include vectors of the form: (p1, x(1); p2, x(2); ..., pm, x(m)), where:
p1 + p2 + ... + pm = 1
A commodity, in this sense, is a lottery. Each superscripted commodity vector x(i) is associated with a probability pi that it will be chosen.

Von Neumann and Morgenstern defined a new set of axioms to go along with their redefined commodity space. One implication is that for any two elements x and y in the commodity space, the linear combination (p, x; (1 - p), y) is also in the space. They obtain that a utility function exists, and it acts like mathematical expectation:
u(p1, x(1); p2, x(2); ..., pm, x(m)) = p1 u(x(1)) + p2 u(x(2)) + ... + pm u(x(m))

Under Von Neumann and Morgenstern's approach, utility functions are only defined up to affine transformations. That is, they are cardinal. In other words, they attain an interval measurement scale level. The utility for a lottery depends only on the probabilities and the resulting outcomes. It does not depend on how many spins of the wheel or roll of the dice are needed to decide between otherwise equivalent lotteries. Gambling is assumed to have no utility or disutility.

Leonard Savage develops axioms of probability concurrently with axioms of utility theory in his personalistic approach to probability and statistics. I'm not sure how much the survey I would like would go into approaches to probability, even if probability is important to decision theory. The same comment applies to game theory.

4.0 Attributes and Needs
Some see commodities as being chosen as an indirect means to choose something more abstract. As I understand it, Kevin Lancaster depicts a commodity as a bundle of attributes. Different commodities can have some attributes in common. A choice of an element in the space of commodities can then be related to an element in a space of commodity attributes.

The early Austrian school economists thought of goods as being desired for the satisfactions of wants. Water, for example, can be used to water your lawn, to satisfy a pet's thirst, or to drink yourself. One can imagine ranking wants in disparate categories. I am thinking of the triangular tables in Chapter III of Carl Menger's Principles of Economics, in Book III, Part A, Chapter III of Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk's Positive Theory of Capital, and in Chapter IV of William Smart's An Introduction to the Theory of Value. The tables are triangular because the most pressing want in one category typically is less pressing than the most pressing want in another category. An element in the space of commodities corresponds to the set of wants that the agent would choose to satisfy with the quantities of commodities specified by that element.

This mapping from quantities of commodities to sets of wants leads to a redefinition of marginal utility, which one might as well designate by a new name - marginal use. The marginal use of a quantity of commodity is, roughly, the different wants that would be added, with a set union, to the set of wants satisfied by the the given quantities of commodities with that additional quantity of the given commodity. McCulloch shows that a ranking of wants in different categories can arise such that a measure does not exist for the space of sets of wants. (A measure in this sense is a technical term in mathematics, typically taught in courses in analysis or advanced courses in the theory of probability.) He argues that the Austrian theory of the marginal use is thus ordinal. Surprisingly, his argument implies that the law of diminishing marginal utility does not require utility to be measured on a cardinal scale.

I haven't read Ian Steedman's work on consumption, but I think I'll mention it here.

5.0 Choices from Menus
Another generalization of the textbook treatment is to examine how a preference relation can be built out of a more fundamental structure. Imagine the agent is presented with a menu, where a menu is a nonempty set of elements of the commodity space. The agent is assumed to have a choice function, which maps each menu to the set of best choices, in some sense, in that menu. The agent is not postulated to rank either the elements not chosen for a given menu or the elements in the choice set.

A question: what constraints need to be put on choices out of menus such that preferences exist? Since a choice function can be constructed for which no preference function exists, some such constraints exist. I previously noted literature drawing on the logical structure of social choice theory in this context. Alan Isaac emphasizes temporal and menu independence in his overview of abstract choice theory.

6.0 Experimental Economics
I am emphasizing theory. A literature exists on experiments, many of which have falsified the textbook treatment of economics.

7.0 Computatibility, Conservation Laws, Etc.
Some of the above extensions of the textbook treatment seem to postulate some sort of structure within the agent's mind. Computers provide an arguable metaphor of mental processes, and some literature applies the theory of computability to economics. Gerald Kramer, for example, shows that no finite automaton can maximize utility in the simplest setting. I gather others have shown that the textbook treatment postulates that each agent's computation powers exceed those of a Turing machine, that agents compute functions that are, in fact, noncomputable. I turn to Kumaraswamy Velupillai's work for insights into computability, constructive mathematics, and economics. Philip Mirowski is always entertaining. One might also mention the literature on Herbert Simon's notion of satisficing

8.0 Conclusion
This post is a brief overview of some of what would be treated in a survey of variations and approaches to utility theory. Apparently, the notion of economic man can be complicated.

An Incomplete List of References
  • Colin F. Camerer (2007) "Neuroeconomics: Using Neuroscience to Make Economic Predictions", Economic Journal, V. 117 (March): C26-C42.
  • Alan G. Isaac (1998) "The Structure of Neoclassical Consumer Theory"
  • Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (1979) "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk" Econometrica, V. 47, N. 2 (March): pp. 263-292
  • Gerald H. Kramer () "An Impossibility Result Concerning the Theory of Decision-Making", Cowles Foundation Paper 274
  • Kevin J. Lancaster (1966) "A New Approach to Consumer Theory", Journal of Political Economy, V. 75: pp. 132-157.
  • J. Huston McCulloch (1977) "The Austrian Theory of the Marginal Use and of Ordinal Marginal Utility", Journal of Economics, V. 37, N. 3-4: pp. 249-280.
  • Judea Pearl (1988) Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference, Morgan Kaufmann
  • Leonard J. Savage (1954, 1972) The Foundations of Statistics, Dover Publications
  • Chris Starmer (1999) "Experimental Economics: Hard Science or Wasteful Tinkering?" Economic Journal, V. 109 (February): pp. F5-F15
  • Ian Steedman (2001) Consumption Takes Time: Implications for Economic Theory, Routledge
  • S. Abu Turab Rizvi (2001) "Preference Formation and the Axioms of Choice", Review of Political Economy, V. 13, N. 12 (Nov.): pp. 141-159
  • John Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (1953) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Third Edition, Princeton University Press

Wednesday, March 03, 2010

Labor Market Flexibility

Some mainstream economists claim that unemployment would be less if labor markets were more flexible and less rigid. In a 1998 paper arguing against this view, Bob Solow explains what this labor market rigidity that so many mainstream economists, especially "freshwater" economists, want to abolish is:
"My first observation is that 'labour-market rigidity' is never defined very precisely or directly in this context, but only be enumeration of tell-tale symptons. Thus a labour market is inflexible if the level of unemployment-insurance benefits is too high or their duration is too long, or if there are too many restrictions on the freedom of employers to fire and to hire, or if the permissible hours of work are too tightly regulated, or if excessively generous compensation for overtime work is mandated, or if trade unions have too much power to protect incumbent workers against competition and to control the flow of work at the site of production, or perhaps if statutory health and safety regulations are too stringent. It seems clear that those who point to labour-market rigidity as the source of high unemployment have something other than simple nominal or real wage rigidity in mind, or so shall I assume." -- Robert M. Solow, "What is Labour-Market Flexibility? What is it Good for?", Proceedings of the British Academy, V. 97
As I understand it, many of these "rigidities" were put in place in the United States context around the time of the New Deal with the cooperation and assistance of Institutionalist economists, a school with some sense of the real world.

Saturday, February 27, 2010

Bank for International Settlements (BIS) - Receptive to Heterodoxy?

I never even heard of the Bank for International Settlements (BIS) before a couple years ago. I am vaguely aware of the Basel accords, which I guess they have something to do with.

I have come across two papers - a ridiculously small number of data points - which make me wonder if they are receptive to heterodox economics. William White, the former chief economist of the BIS, criticized last December the direction of research in modern macroeconomics. He thinks macroeconomists should pay more attention to Hyman Minsky and also Austrian Business Cycle Theory. In a current BIS working paper (H/T to D-Squared), Piti Disyatat rejects the loanable funds theory and argues for the theory of an endogenous money supply, if I understand correctly. This paper references, among others, Basil Moore, Thomas Palley, and Randy Wray.

Tuesday, February 23, 2010

Colin Rogers and Ian Steedman Down Under

Colin Rogers has a review essay of Geoff Tily's Keynes's General Theory, the Rate of Interest and 'Keynesian' Economics: Keynes Betrayed:
"Tily (chapter 4) carefully documents how this Robertson version of 'Keynesian' economics succeeded in squeezing out Keynes' vision. The model behind Robertson’s vision is instantly recognisable by all students of economics today and consists of the idea that there exists a unique long-run equilibrium around which the economy fluctuates during booms and recessions... Apart from the fact that Keynes ... described rigidities as the classical explanation for unemployment, Tily makes it clear that this 'Keynesian' interpretation overlooks entirely that Keynes was concerned with the existence of multiple long-period equilibria in the General Theory. -- Colin Rogers, "Keynes vs the Keynesians: Keynes Rediscovered", History of Economics Review, Winter 2008.
I have never quite understood the idea that Keynesian policy is about helping the economy reach equilibrium quicker. I thought The Arrow-Debreu model of intertemporal equilibria was the canonical neoclassical explanation of prices. That model doesn't allow for out-of-equilibrium behavior in real time. By now, it should be trivial to create models of multiple long-run equilibria. Keynes' explanation for multiple long-run equilibria, I think, had to do with long-run expectations - each state of expectations creates a different (set of?) long run equilibrium.

Ian Steedman reviews another volume in Hayek's collected works:
"Laurence White has been zealous in providing editorial footnotes to Hayek’s text and many of his notes are indeed helpful... Some footnotes seem to be quite unnecessary explications... The simple observation by Hayek, that the choice of production method may change in response to a relative input price change, is made the occasion of a long and irrelevant note on the 'economics of socialism' debate..., while an editorial reference to the 'reswitching controversy' cites a single discussion thereof – one by Leland Yeager! ... It might be felt here that Hayek’s text is being used for the promotion of ‘Austrian’ economics more generally." -- Ian Steedman on "F. A. Hayek. The Pure Theory of Capital. Volume 12 of the Collected Works of F. A. Hayek, History of Economics Review, Summer 2009.

Saturday, February 20, 2010

Fred Lee's New History of Heterodox Economics

Frederick Lee has written a book: A History of Heterodox Economics: Challenging the Mainstream in the Twentieth Century. I don't know if I'm going to purchase this Routledge book. I've read papers many of the chapters grew from.

Saturday, February 13, 2010

Alex Haley and John Maynard Keynes: Self-Confident Authors

Alex Haley used to hang out at the Savoy, a local restraurant in Rome, NY. While writing Roots, he told the owner, "I am writing a book that is going to change how white people look at black people in America."

While writing The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money, Keynes had an argument with George Bernard Shaw about Marx. Keynes wrote to Shaw on 1 January 1935:
"...To understand my state of mind, however, you have to know that I believe myself to be writing a book on economic theory, which will largely revolutionise - not, I suppose, at once but in the course of the next ten years - the way the world thinks about economic problems. When my new theory has been duly assimilated and mixed with politics and feelings and passions, I can't predict what the upshot will be in its effects on actions and affairs. But there will be a great change, and, in particular, the Ricardian foundations of Marxism will be knocked away.

I can't expect you, or anyone else, to believe this at the present stage. But for myself I don't merely hope what I say, - in my own mind I'm quite sure."
I don't accept that Marx built on Say's Law, which is what Keynes refuted.

Tuesday, February 09, 2010

Notre Dame Faculty Senate Defends Academic Freedom

Maybe Phil Mirowski and his more interesting colleagues will be able to pursue their vocation.

Saturday, February 06, 2010

Garrison Orally On Reswitching

The following is from the Question and Answer session for Roger Garrison's recent lecture, "Macroeconomics: The Boom and Bust Cycle" (starting at about 59:29):
Audience member: "Can you reconcile using Hayekian triangles with reswitching and [unclear]?"

Garrison: "Yeah. The question is, 'How do you reconcile the Hayekian triangle with the Cambridge Capital Controversy, which involves capital-reswitching and technique reversing. I got that backwards - isn't it technique reswitching and capital reversing. Let me just take a poll here. How many have heard of the Cambridge Capital Controversy and know about technique reswitching and capital-reversing? Good, OK, good. One guy.

Let me just give you a standing-on-one-foot explanation. Capital theorists in Cambridge - this is Cambridge, England - argued that Böhm-Bawerk didn't have it quite right. His math was too simple, and if you allow for inputs and outputs to be expressed by polynomials, instead of rectangles or linear inputs, you find that the production process could lengthen or shorten with the change in the interest rate. If the interest rate falls, maybe it will shorten, or maybe it will lengthen. And you don't know. You have to look at the math and see how it turns out.

And the way the math turns out, there are only trivial exceptions - very small exceptions to the proposition that a low interest rate encourages long-term investment. You can come up with counterexamples, but even Cambridge capital-theorists, like Joan Robinson - she wrote an article, "The Unimportance of Reswitching" - just the magnitude doesn't amount to anything. If you read Hayek's Pure Theory of Capital, he acknowledges that, yes, yes, you can have funny profiles that seem to run counter to the general proposition that a low interest rate encourages long-term production. But those are very trivial. I've published articles on this. I can give you a link to one. But one thing I observed is that to get numbers where the reswitching is visible to the naked eye, you have to have the interest rate changing from 100% to 50%, or something like that, which itself suggests how minor that distinction is.

There are actually more fundamental criticisms that are based on how the Cambridge capital theorists measure roundaboutness. And the Austrians don't really measure it. They don't need to measure it. It's enough to show you the pictures. You saw the picture of the Research and Development chemist. You saw the picture of the retail clerk. That's what we are talking about, however you describe that mathematically. So I think, economically, that just doesn't work.

There are economists - Post Keynesians are the main ones - who throw up that Cambridge Capital Controversy as a killer of Austrian Business Cycle theory. They see that as the basis for just dismissing Austrian Business Cycle theory, but I think with very little justification."

References:
  • Roger M. Garrison (1979) "Comment: Waiting in Vienna", in Time, Uncertainty and Disequilibrium: Exploration of Austrian Themes (ed. by M. J. Rizzo), D. C. Heath and Company
  • Roger M. Garrison (2006) "Reflections on Reswitching and Roundaboutness", in Money and the Markets: Essays in Honor of Leland Yeager (ed. by R. Kopl), New York:Routledge.

Sunday, January 31, 2010

Austrian Business Cycle Theory As Uninteresting And Esoteric

I have been unsuccessful in getting my refutation of Austrian Business Cycle Theory accepted for publication in a peer-reviewed journal. My latest publically available version is downloadable from SSRN. I have had a later version rejected a couple of weeks ago. This version's references include Roger Garrison's 2006 "Reflections on Reswitching and Roundaboutness". I hope quoting an extract from a review is acceptable, since some might find this of interest:
"Hayek had washed his hands of the triangles [that ground his theory of the trade cycle] long before the ink was dry on his Pure Theory of Capital... Modern Austrian school economists like Roger Garrison still find the triangle-logic compelling, but I have the impression that, with the possible exception of Leland Yeager’s 1976 Economic Inquiry paper, no systematic attempt has been made to show that Austrian economics is immune to the capital critique; the arguments are intuitive rather than carefully drawn. (Even Yeager’s piece struck me when I read it, many years ago, as largely intuitive.) ...the arguments had never been put forward in a robust way..."

Tuesday, January 26, 2010

Classical Cross Dual Dynamics

"The actual price at which any commodity is commonly sold is called its market price. It may either be above, or below, or exactly the same with its natural price.

The market price of every particular commodity is regulated by the proportion between the quantity which is actually brought to market, and the demand of those who are willing to pay the natural price of the commodity, or the whole value of the rent, labour, and profit, which must be paid in order to bring it thither. Such people may be called the effectual demanders, and their demand the effectual demand; since it may be sufficient to effectuate the bringing of the commodity to market...

...The natural price, therefore, is, as it were, the central price, to which the prices of all commodities are continually gravitating...

The whole quantity of industry annually employed in order to bring any commodity to market, naturally suits itself in this manner to the effectual demand. It naturally aims at bringing always that precise quantity thither which may be sufficient to supply, and no more than supply this demand." - Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, Book I, Chapter VII


1.0 Introduction
Contemporary economists have elaborated Smith's metaphor of the gravitational attraction of market prices to natural prices. Elaborations consist of formal models of cross-dual dynamics.

Systems of equations describing prices and quantitites are dual systems in the post Sraffa/von Neumann tradition. Dynamics are cross dual when changes in prices respond to quantities and changes in quantities respond to prices. In particular, industries expand in which rates of profits are high and contract in industries in which profits are low. And prices fall in industries in which the quantity supplied exceeds the effectual demand. Prices rise in industries in which the quantity supplied is below the effectual demand.

Dupertuis and Sinha (2009) is one immediate impetus for my setting out this model of the reallocation of labor for a given wage. I don't think I thoroughly understand models of cross-dual dynamics. I think they are of interest for exploring the possible dynamics of market prices in competitive capitalist economies. I don't see that they are directly empirically applicable. For that, one needs to worry about markup prices and the degree of utilization of capacity in various industries.

2.0 Natural Prices
The data of our problem are:
  • The n x n input-output matrix A, where n is the number of industries and ai, j is the amount of the ith commodity used as input per unit output of the jth industry
  • The n-element row vector a0 of labor inputs, where a0, j is the amount of person-hours hired per unit output in the jth industry
  • The money wage wgiven
  • The composition of net output as expressed in the n-element column vector cgiven.
This is a circulating capital model in which all production processes use up their inputs in a year. Labor is assumed to be paid their wages at the end of the year. Only economies capable of producing a surplus product are considered. For simplicity, assume Constant Returns to Scale (CRS) and that every commodity is basic, in Sraffa's sense. This section considers the problem of finding:
  • The natural prices, as expressed in the n-element row vector p*
  • The corresponding wages w*
  • The corresponding rate of profits r*
  • The effectual demand as expressed in the n-element column vector of gross quantities q*
  • The n-element column vector of net quantities y*.

In the system of natural prices, the same rate of profits are made in every industry:
p* A(1 + r*) + a0 w* = p*
I take the net output as the numeraire.
p* y* = 1
In my formulation here, the wage is taken as a given ratio of the net output:
w* = wgiven
The above equations comprise the price system for natural prices.

Net outputs and gross outputs are related by the following equation:
y* = q* - A q* = (I - A) q*
where I is the identity matrix. I normalize the units of labor such that one unit is employed throughout the economy:
a0 q* = 1
Finally, the net output is assumed to be in the specified proportions. That is, there exists a positive constant k such that
y* = k cgiven

The above systems of equations are sufficient to determine gross and net effectual demands, natural prices, and the distribution of income. (An alternative specification would take the composition of gross output as given, instead of the net output. Perhaps outputs should be in units of Sraffa's standard commodity.)

3.0 Initial Condititions
The problem in the remaining sections is to define a dynamic process for the quantities produced q(t) and the market prices p(t) for t = 0, 1, 2, ... The initial quantities q(0) and market prices p(0) are givens. For the sake of the argument, I consider a dynamic process in which the amount of labor employed and the value of net output are invariant. So the initial quantities and prices must satisfy the following equations:
a0 q(0) = 1

p(0) y(0) = p(0)(I - A)q(0) = 1

4.0 Reallocation of Labor
Define raverage(t), the average rate of profits for the economy as a whole at time t:
raverage(t) = [p(t)(I - A - a0 wgiven)q(t)]/[p(t) A q(t)]
The numerator in the expression on the right hand side above is the value of the surplus product remaining in the capitalists' possession after replacing the means of production and paying laborers their wages. The denominator is the value of the capital goods advanced.

Typically, the rate of profits will vary from the average among the industries. The rate of profits for the jth industry at time t is:
rj(t) = [pj(t) - p(t) a., j - a0, j wgiven]/[p(t) a., j]
where a., j is the jth column of the input-output matrix A.

Define Raverage(t) to be the n-element column vector with each element equal to the average rate of profits. Let R(t) be the n-element column vector with each element being the rate of profits for the corresponding sector.

Now dynamics of the quantities of produced commodities can be specified:
q(t + 1) = [1/f1(t)]{[R(t) - Raverage(t)] + q(t)}
Or, in terms of scalars:
qi(t + 1) = [1/f1(t)]{[ri(t) - raverage(t)] + qi(t)}
where
f1(t) = 1 + a0[R(t) - Raverage(t)]
The denominator f1(t) above is a normalization that ensures the quantity of labor employed is always unity. The numerator ensures that the more the rate of profits in a sector exceeds the average, the faster that sector will expand in comparison with other sectors. (An alternative formulation might compare the rate of profits in each industry with the rate of profits r* in the system of natural prices.)

5.0 Price Changes
Price dynamics are here set out more directly:
p(t + 1) = [1/f2(t)]{p(t) - [qT(t) - q*T]}
where xT is the transpose of the vector x. In terms of scalars, prices are given by:
pi(t + 1) = [1/f2(t)]{pi(t)- [qi(t) - q*i]}
The time series f2(t) is defined as follows:
f2(t) = [q*T - qT(t)](I - A)q(t + 1)} + p(t)(I - A)q(t + 1)
The denominator f2(t) above is, again, a normalization condition. In this case, the normalization ensures the value of the net output is equal to unity. Since the composition of net output typically changes over the course of the process, the real wage varies in terms of any fixed commodity basket. It does remain, however, a given ratio of the net output.

6.0 Conclusion
I have set out above a model of a dynamic process, but without an analysis of its properties. An obvious theorem is that if initial quantities and prices happen to be equal to the effectual demands and natural prices, they will be left unchanged by the dynamics of market adjustments. In other words, the natural system is a stationary point of this dynamic process.

An interesting question is the trajectory of market prices, given an arbitrary starting point. I don't expect the process to necessarily converge to the natural system. At this point, I don't have any numeric examples of limit cycles or chaotic behavior. A failure of local stability doesn't bother me; I have often thought of Sraffa's work as pointing towards the possibility of complex dynamics arising in models of capitalist economies.

Questions of structural stability are of interest as well. Do dynamic properties of the system depend on the level of wages, especially if one introduces into the model a choice of technique? And how do the answers to these questions vary, if at all, with alternative modeling assumptions, some of which I have indicated? I do not know that the literature has reached definitive answers to these questions.

Update (28 January 2010): I have redefined the dynamics above in a way that seems more reasonable to me.

References
  • Michel-Stéphane Dupertuis and Ajit Sinha, "A Sraffian Critique of the Classical Notion of Centre of Gravitation", Cambridge Journal of Economics, V. 33 (2009): 1065-1087.

Sunday, January 24, 2010

Upcoming URPE Conferences

Chris Pepin informs us that the Union for Radical Political Economics (URPE) will participate in the upcoming Eastern Economics Association (EEA) conference. The conference will be held at the Loews Philadelphia Hotel, February 26 - 28. A program is available. This year is the 50th anniversary of the publication of Sraffa's book.

URPE is also participating in the Left Forum, on March 19-21 at Pace University.

Elsewhere

  • Eric Rauchway tells us about the Bretton Woods conference, where John Maynard Keynes showed that some economists could be more useful than dentists.
  • David Ruccio reprints a cartoon by B. Deutsch making fun of economists prefering a supposedly elegant theory of the minimum wage to empirical results falsifying the theory.
  • Bill Mitchell has a negative view of Greg Mankiw's textbook.

Wednesday, January 20, 2010

Skimming Moshe Adler

A few weeks ago, in a bookstore a couple of hundred miles away from here, I skimmed Moshe Adler's Economics for the Rest of Us: Debunking the Science that Makes Life Dismal. I did not purchase it because I am already too far behind in my reading. It is targeted for those outside the economics profession.

It is a short and approachable book that, as I recall, falls into two main parts.

The first part is about the mainstream economist's concept of (Pareto) efficiency. I hopped over this section fairly quickly, since I see no need to be strongly guided by this criterion in making policy decisions. I gather Adler agrees.

The second part is about income distribution, the theory of marginal productivity, and wages. Adler compares and contrasts neoclassical theory and the more empirically applicable classical theory. If I read this book in more depth, I would probably have some caveats about Adler's interpretation of the classical economists and his assignment to them of one (non-Malthusian) theory of wages. Adler recognizes that in a theory in which wages are determined by well-behaved supply and demand functions for labor, the imposition of higher wages results in less employment. Less security and less employment is a bad thing for many members of that vast majority in capitalist societies who depend on income from labor to live. On the other hand, when wages are the result of class struggle, as in Adam Smith, for example, the theory does not predict that unions, minimum wages, less "flexible" labor markets will result in less employment. And, despite the poppycock mainstream economists teach, that is the world we live in.

I agree with the author. Economics took a mostly wrong turning more than a century ago. I don't think that this book will convince many mainstream economists. If Adler wanted to convince mainstream economists, he would have had to written a more impenetrable book. I think Adler does address some of the questions raised by the current global economic crisis.

(I realize I am behind in responding to comments on previous posts.)

Saturday, January 16, 2010

The First Communist

One can find all sorts of things on the internet, such as T-shirts.


And one can find lots of silliness: "Why Jesus Christ is Not a Communist".

Hat tip: My friend Lucas.

Sunday, January 10, 2010

Leontief's Work As Applied Sraffianism

Sraffa's critique is formulated in terms of physical quantity flows among industries and labor inputs into each industry. From this data, institutional assumptions, and, for example, the rate of profits, Sraffa deduces the set of constant prices that allow for the smooth reproduction of a capitalist economy.

Leontief independently developed the theory of Input-Output (I-O) analysis, and national income accounts include I-O accounts. The Bureau of Economic Analysis maintains I-O accounts for the United States.

A body of work exists in which the national income accounts are used to examine empirical questions. Sometimes the output of each industry is normalized to one physical unit of each industry, thereby allowing the national accounts to be thought of as closer to Sraffa’s data. Much of this work can be seen as classical in approach, not marginalist. Benjamin H. Mitra-Kahn's "Debunking the Myths of Computable General Equilibrium Models" (2008) shows that the classical nature of one such body of empirical work is often disguised by tendentious and incorrect history.

So Sraffa’s work is empirically applicable, although his own intentions seem to have been more focused on criticism.

Saturday, January 02, 2010

Mainstream Economists Unable To Discuss Economics

Over on Economics Job Market Rumors, an anonymous poster asks:
"Despite the neoclassicals admitting that the Post-Keynesians were right, why has the impact of heterogeneous capital on an economy left out of the macro models?"
It will not surprise me if he or she receives no coherent answer. I recently had a chance to skim the transcripts of David Colander's interviews with graduate students at the "best" economics departments in the United States. These are in his book The Making of an Economist Redux. The following phrases seem no connote nothing to such students: "Cambridge Capital Controversy", "Neoclassical Economics", and "Post Keynesian Economics". One student responded to a question about Joan Robinson by asking, "Who's that?" The best students seem to realize that they will have to get an education by themselves in their "spare" time after they receive their doctorate.

Friday, January 01, 2010

Minimum Wages In The U.K.

The Australian Fair Pay Commission's Minimum Wage Research Forum met in Melbourne on 30 and 31 October 2008. Stephen Machin summarized recent experience in the United Kingdom (in the 2008 Minimum Wage Research Forum Proceedings, Volume 1).

Minimum wages were set by industry in the United Kingdom up until 1993. The wage councils were abolished in 1993, except for the Agriculture Wages Board which continues to this day. Outside of agriculture, the UK did not have a minimum wage between 1993 and 1999. From 1999 on, the National Minimum Wage was in effect in the UK, as recommended by the UK Low Pay Commission, established in 1997 by the newly elected Labour government. Notice that the trend in employment visually appears unaffected by the introduction of the national minimum wage and subsequent increases in it. The trend appears the same before as afterwards. This seems like disconfirmatory evidence to me of the simple neoclassical model of wages and employment as determined by supply and demand functions. Some of us know that model is without theoretical foundation anyways.

Hat tip to Bill Mitchell

Sunday, December 27, 2009

Parallel Thoughts By Wittgenstein And Sraffa

Apparently Wittgenstein wrote the following in 1937:
"The origin and the primitive form of the language game is a reaction; only from this can more complicated forms develop.

Language - I want to say - is a refinement, 'in the beginning was the deed'." -- Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value (Translated by Peter Winch) (1980)
And Sraffa, I guess, wrote the following in the early 1930s:
"If the rules of language can be constructed only by observation, there can never be any nonsense said. This identifies the cause and the meaning of a word.

The language of birds, as well as the language of metaphysicians can be interpreted consistently in this way.

It is only a matter of finding the occasion on which they say a thing, just as one finds the occasion on which they sneeze.

And if nonsense is 'a mere noise' it certainly must happen, as sneeze, when there is cause: how can this be distinguished from its meaning?

We should give up the generalities and take particular cases, from which we started. Take conditional propositions: whan are they nonsense, and when are they not?" -- Piero Sraffa as quoted by Heinz D. Kurz, "'If some people looked like elephants and others like cats, or fish...' On the difficulties of understanding each other: the case of Wittgenstein and Sraffa", The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, V. 16, n. 2 (2009): pp. 361-374

Monday, December 21, 2009

Colander Testimony On Risks Modeling

Last September, the Committee on Science and Technology's Subcommittee on Investigations and Oversight, a subcommittee of the United States House of Representatives heard testimony on the risks of financial modeling. I looked at David Colander's testimony.

Colander advocates modeling economies as complex dynamical systems. He thinks economists should be aware of the limitations of models. Macroeconomists, in settling on the Dynamic Stochastic General Equilibrium (DSGE) model, failed to consider a wide range of models. The assumptions of the DSGE model do not fit the real world. (In objecting to the use of the "assumption" of the existence of a representative agent, I am on the side of such economists as Alan Kirman and Frank Hahn & Robert Solow.)

Colander discusses how mainstream economists are indoctrinated. Colander recommends that peer review for grants from the National Science Foundation for economics research include, "for example, physicists, mathematician[s], statisticans, and even business and govermental representatives".

This bit about the NSF reminds me of a story Paul Davidson tells:
"In 1980 I applied for a grant from the National Science Foundation to write International Money and the Real World... One of the [insider peer reviewers] had the most telling observation of them all. He said something like, 'It is true that Davidson has a very good track record and surprisingly good publications, but he marches to a different drummer. If he's marching to a different drummer, if his music is different, then he ought to get his own money and not use ours.'" -- Paul Davidson in J. E. King, Conversations with Post Keynesians (1995)
Davidson did not get the grant.

Saturday, December 19, 2009

Weird Science II

A bit from Avatar reminds me of Ursula K. LeGuin's "Vaster Than Empires and More Slow", a short story republished in her collection The Wind's Twelve Quarters (1975). LeGuin postulates a world in which nodes in tree roots act like synapses. The plant life is one sentience. Maybe even vines and spores partake in it. As before, a cultural work reminds me of some science:
  • The longest lived thing is arguably Pando, a grove of aspens in Utah that seems to be one plant, connected at the roots and propagating through runners like strawberries or mrytle.
  • Or maybe it is an instance of the fungus Armillaria bulbosa in Oregon.
A Wikipedia article lists other such organisms, for what it's worth. (The references in this post are reminders for me to look up sometime.)

Monday, December 14, 2009

Wage-Rate Of Profits Curves

1.0 Introduction
I have written about so-called factor price curves and frontiers in many posts. They are so-called because the interest rate is not a price of any factor of production. In this post, I use the more neutral expressions "Wage-Rate of Profits Curve" and "Wage-Rate of Profits Frontier". I consider the concepts denoted by these terms to be elements of mathematical economics that arise, in particular, in the analysis of steady states.

2.0 Derivation of a Wage-Rate of Profits Curve
Consider an economy in which n commodities are produced. Each commodity j is produced in a corresponding industry in which it is the sole output of a single process. This process:
  • Requires inputs of labor and commodities. These inputs are represented as a0, j person-years per unit output and ai, j units of the ith commodity per unit output.
  • Exhibits Constant Returns to Scale (CRS).
  • Requires a year to complete.
  • Totally uses up its commodity inputs.
A technique consists of a process for each of the n industries. The technique is represented by the row vector a0 of direct labor coefficients and the square Leontief Input-Output matrix A. Assume:
  • Each commodity enters either directly or indirectly into the production of all commodities. That is, all commodities are basic in the sense of Sraffa.
  • The economy is viable. That is, there exists a level of operation of all processes such that the outputs can replace the commodities used up in their production and leave a surplus product to be paid out in the form of wages and profits.
  • Wages are paid at the end of the year.
  • The same rate of profits is earned on advances in all industries.
The assumptions of CRS and of all commodities being basic are made for ease of exposition.

Under these assumptions, the constant prices that allow the economy to smoothly reproduce satisfy the following system of n equations:
p A (1 + r) +w a0 = p
where p is the row vector of prices, w is the wage, and r is the rate of profits. Given the rate of profits, this is a linear system in n + 1 variables. The last equation imposed in the model sets the value of the numeraire to unity:
p e = 1
where e is a column vector denoting the units of each commodity that comprise the numeraire. Only solutions in which all prices are positive and the wage is non-negative are considered.

The price equation can be transformed into:
w a0 = p [I - (1 + r)A]
where I is the identity matrix. Or:
w a0 [I - (1 + r)A]-1 = p
where the assumption of viability guarantees the existence of the inverse for all rates of profits between zero and a maximum rate of profits. Right multiply both sides of the above equation by the numeraire:
w a0 [I - (1 + r)A]-1 e = p e = 1
The wage-rate of profits curve for the technique is then:
w = 1/{a0 [I - (1 + r)A]-1 e}

3.0 Properties of Wage-Rate of Profits Curves
The Wage-Rate of Profits Curve for a technique, under the assumptions above, has the following properties:
  • There is a finite maximum rate of profits for which the wage is zero. (If no commodity were basic, this maximum would not be finite.)
  • There is a maximum wage for which the rate of profits is zero.
  • The wage-rate of profits curve is strictly decreasing between the rate of profits of zero and the maximum rate of profits.
  • The wage rate of profits curve can be both convex to the origin and concave to the origin. (If the number of commodities n is greater than 2, the convexity can vary throughout the curve.)
  • If the vector of direct labor coeffients is a left-hand eigenvector of the Leontief Input-Output matrix, the wage-rate of profits curve is a straight line, that is, affine. (This is Marx's case of equal organic composition of capitals.)
  • If the numeraire is a right-hand eigenvector of the Leontief Input-Output matrix, the wage-rate of profits curve is affine. (This is the case of Sraffa's standard commodity.)
Figure 1 illustrates the wage-rate of profits curve for five techniques (α, β, δ, ε, and τ). Pasinetti uses π, not r, to denote the rate of profits. These curves are drawn under the assumption that the organic composition of capitals is not constant for any technique, and the numeraire is not the standard commodity for any of the techniques. Figure 1 also shows the wage-rate of profits frontier, formed from the outer envelope of all the wage-rate of profits curves for the individual techniques. This frontier is used to analyze the choice of technique for long-period, circulating capital models with single production.
Figure 1: The Frontier Formed From Factor-Price Curves (from Pasinetti (1977), p. 157)

Selected References
  • Heinz D. Kurz and Neri Salvadori (1995) Theory of Production: A Long-Period Analysis, Cambridge University Press
  • Heinz D. Kurz and Neri Salvadori "Production Theory: An Introduction"
  • Luigi L. Pasinetti (1977) Lectures on the Theory of Production, Columbia University Press

Paul A. Samuelson, 1915-2009

I've been influenced by Samuelson's work. I've referenced him here on such topics as:
  • Aggregate production functions
  • Cambridge Capital Controversies, Joan Robinson, and Piero Sraffa
  • Growth theory
  • International trade, theory of
  • Linear programming
  • Marginal productivity theory
  • Marxist economics
  • Revealed preference theory
I don't think I've referenced him on overlapping generations models when I've used them. But I believe he originated such models.

Wednesday, December 09, 2009

Negative Price Wicksell Effect, Positive Real Wicksell Effect

1.0 Introduction
I have previously suggested a taxonomy of Wicksell effects. This post presents an example with:
  • The cost-minimizing technique varying continuously along the so-called factor-price frontier
  • Negative price Wicksell effects
  • Positive real Wicksell effects
  • Price Wicksell effects greater in magnitude than real Wicksell effects.
This example is due to Saverio M. Fratini ("Reswitching and Decreasing Demand for Capital").

2.0 Technology
Suppose technology consists of a continuum of techniques indexed by the parameter θ, where θ is a real number restricted to the interval [0, 1]:
0 ≤ θ ≤ 1
Each technique consists of the three Constant-Returns-to-Scale processes in Table 1. No commodity is basic, in Sraffa's sense, in any technique in this technology. In the first process in a technique, θ-grade iron is produced directly from unassisted labor. In the second process, labor transforms the θ-grade iron into θ-grade steel. Finally, in the third process, labor transforms θ-grade steel into corn, the consumption good in the model. All processes take a year to complete, and all processes totally use up their input.
Table 1: The Technique Indexed by θ
InputsIndustry Sector
θ-Grade
Iron
θ-Grade
Steel
Corn
Labor (Person-Yrs)1/(1 + θ)θ3/(1 + θ)
Iron (Tons)010
Steel (Tons)001
Corn (Bushels)000
Output1 Ton1 Ton1 Bushel
Capital goods are specific in their uses in this example. θ1-grade steel cannot be made out of θ2-grade iron when θ1 ≠ θ2.

3.0 Stationary-State Quantity Flows
Suppose in Table 1 that:
  • The first process is used to produce (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) tons of θ-grade iron
  • The second process is used to produce (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) tons of θ-grade steel
  • The third process is used to produce (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) bushels corn
Then one person-year would be employed over these three processes. Capital goods would consist of (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) tons of θ-grade iron and (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) tons of θ-grade steel. The capital goods would be used up throughout the latter two sectors, but reproduced at the end of the year. Net output would consist of (1 + θ)/(4 + θ + θ2) bushels corn per person-year.

4.0 Prices
Given the technique, stationary state prices must satisfy the following three equations:
[1/(1 + θ)] w = p1
p1(1 + r) + θ w = p2
p2(1 + r) + [3/(1 + θ)] w = 1
where:
  • p1 is the price of a ton θ-grade iron;
  • p2 is the price of a ton θ-grade steel;
  • w is the wage;
  • r is the rate of profits.
A bushel corn is the numeraire. The above equations embody the assumption that labor is paid at the end of the year.

The above is a system of three equations in four unknowns, given the technique. It is a linear system, given the rate of profits. The solution in terms of the rate of profits is easily found. The so-called factor-price curve for a technique is:
w(r, θ) = (1 + θ)/[3 + θ(1 + θ)(1 + r) + (1 + r)2]
The price of a ton θ-grade iron is:
p1(r, θ) = 1/[3 + θ(1 + θ)(1 + r) + (1 + r)2]
The price of a ton θ-grade steel is:
p2(r, θ) = [(1 + r) + θ(1 + θ)]/[3 + θ(1 + θ)(1 + r) + (1 + r)2]
Given the technique and the rate of profits, these prices can be used to evaluate the value of the capital goods used in a stationary state.

5.0 The Cost-Minimizing Technique
The optimal technique to use at any given rate of profits maximizes the wage. The first-order condition for such maximization is found by equating the derivative of the factor-price curve to zero:
dw/dθ = 0
Or:
3 + θ(1 + θ)(1 + r) + (1 + r)2 - (1 + θ)(1 + 2θ)(1 + r) = 0
For 0 ≤ r ≤ 2, the cost-minimizing technique is then:
θ(r) = {[3 + (1 + r)2]/(1 + r)}1/2 - 1
For r > 2, a corner solution is found:
θ(r) = 1
Figure 1 illustrates the cost-minimizing technique.
Figure 1: The Choice of Technique
The graph in Figure 1 reaches a minimum at a rate of profits of (31/2 - 1). For (121/4 - 1) < θ < 1, two rate of profits have the corresponding cost-minimizing technique indexed by the given value of θ. In other words, this is an example of reswitching.

The index for the cost-minimizing technique can be plugged into the factor price curve for the technique to which it corresponds at a given rate of profits. Figure 2 displays the resulting so-called factor price frontier. The index θ varies continuously for 0 ≤ r ≤ 200% in Figure 2. As the rate of profits increases without bound, the frontier approaches a wage of zero.

Figure 2: The Factor-Price Frontier


6.0 Capital and Labor "Markets"
Fratini’s notes that this is a reswitching example in which the capital market initially appears to be in accord with out-dated neoclassical intuition. The above analysis has shown how to find physical quantities of capital goods per worker, how to evaluate them at equilibrium prices, and how to find net output per worker. Figure 3 shows the resulting plot of the value of capital per unit output. Fratini looks at the value of capital per worker instead. Either curve is continuous and downward-sloping. The regions above and below the rate of profits of (31/2 - 1) appear qualitatively similar and visually indistinguishable. This curve might be said to be a downward-sloping demand function for capital.
Figure 3: The Capital Market
The analogous curve looks very different for the labor market (Figure 4). The region with a positive Wicksell effect is a region with a high rate of profits and thus a low real wage. The demand function for labor might be said to be upward-sloping in the region with a positive real Wicksell effect.
Figure 4: The Labor Market

7.0 Conclusion
The example makes Fratini’s point. The shape of the relationship between the value of capital, either per worker or per unit output, and the rate of profits is not necessarily a good indicator of the presence of reswitching or reverse capital-deepening.

Saturday, December 05, 2009

Two Blogs Critical Of Economics

The post-autistic movement now has a blog: The Real-World Economics Review Blog.

I'm much less enthusiastic about the Counter-Economics Blog, which I stumbled over recently. Shaun Snapp claims to be applying critical thinking to economics, but he is too popular and too focused on finance for my taste. His claim that nobody reads either Adam Smith or Karl Marx is belied by the many serious scholars that do. (I've read major works by both.)

Wednesday, December 02, 2009

Herbert Gintis, Amazon Reviewer

Herb Gintis has now posted 231 reviews to Amazon. He has something to anger everybody.

Here he describes Jerry Cohen as a "supporter of virtually unsupportable Marxian doctrines" and having "studied ignorance of standard social and psychological theory."

He gives only two stars to Keen's Debunking Economics because, according to Gintis, it attacks a straw person. Mainstream economics is not as depicted by Keen, only undergraduate teaching is. "Abjectly brainless", "often just plain wrong", and "like teaching ... phlogiston and ether in physics class" are Gintis' phrases. I like how defenders of the mainstream cannot and will not defend economics as taught.

Gintis also gives only two stars to Ontology and Economics: Tony Lawson and His Critics. Basically, he disagrees that "Lawson's arguments are so powerful that few economists now feel that his case can be ignored." According to Gintis, his case can too be ignored; economists just ignore methodology. Gintis doesn't really engage the give and take in the book. I think he should have noted his agreement with John Davis's take on the openness of mainstream economics to some kinds of heterodox contributions.

I found this review of a recent George Soros book of interest. Some blame the current financial meltdown on failures of either individual or collective rationality. Gintis says that even if everybody were as rational as some (Chicago?) economists posit, market fundamentalism would still be unfounded. He bases this claim on the failure of the Arrow-Debreu model of General Equilibrium to have any attractive dynamical properties. He recommends agent-based modeling to analyze capitalist economies.

Gintis has quite a few positive reviews of rightists. For example, he gives four stars to Hazlitt's Economics in One Lesson. (Despite most of the reviews I'm highlighting, he also has some extremely positive reviews for liberals and leftists.) I think his reviews of right wing books generate more comments, and Gintis replies. (The worst are full of passionate intensity.) One review of a book that I would think is not worth reading currently has 103 comments.

In addition to politics and economics, he has also reviewed books on language, biology, and logic. I want to recall the existence of Torkel Franzen's Godel's Theorem: An Incomplete Guide to Its Use and Abuse.

Sunday, November 29, 2009

A Taxonomy Of The Effects Of Wicksell Effects

Consider a typical circulating capital model, in which commodities are produced from commodities and labor. The technique in use is described by a square Leontief input-output matrix and a vector of labor coefficients. In a long run equilibrium, in which prices are stationary, the technique is selected from a set of techniques to minimize production costs at a given interest rate. That set is known as the technology.

Suppose the composition and quantity of output is taken as given, along with the interest rate and the technology. The difference in the value of the capital goods at two different interest rates is the sum of the price Wicksell and real Wicksell effects. The price Wicksell effect is the sum of the differences in prices among the capital goods for a given technique. But the cost-minimizing technique might not be the same at two interest rates. The real Wicksell effect is the difference in the value of the capital goods for two techniques, given the price system at a one interest rate.

I want to compare the relative magnitude of price and real Wicksell effects at a given interest rate. Thus, I want to consider derivatives at a given interest rate. Therefore, suppose the technology consists of a continuum of techniques that might be eligible along the so-called factor price frontier. Table 1 shows all combinations of price and real Wicksell effects. A Wicksell effect is negative when the equilibrium at the higher interest rate has a lower value of capital, from the effects of price and quantity changes, respectively.

Table 1: Possibilities
Technology PropertyLabor
Market
Response
Capital
Market
Response
Price
Wicksell
Effects
Real
Wicksell
Effects
Higher
Wage
Lower
Interest
Rate
ANegativeNegativeLess
Employment
Increased
Value of
Capital
BNegativePositiveMore
Employment
Indeterminate
CPositiveNegativeLess
Employment
Indeterminate
DPositivePositiveMore
Employment
Decreased
Value of
Capital
EZeroNegativeLess
Employment
Increased
Value of
Capital
F?ZeroPositiveMore
Employment
Decreased
Value of
Capital
GNegativeZeroUnchanged
Employment
Increased
Value of
Capital
HPositiveZeroUnchanged
Employment
Decreased
Value of
Capital
IZeroZeroUnchanged
Employment
Unchanged
Value of
Capital

Row A in Table 1 conforms to the outdated neoclassical intuition of equilibrium prices as indices of relative scarcity. But, as Edwin Burmeister has noted, nobody knows what special case assumptions need to be imposed on technology to ensure that Wicksell effects happen to fall in any given direction.

I have the response in the capital market shown as indeterminate for rows B and C. The claim is that, for the case of a technology representable by a continuum of techniques, the price Wicksell effect can, but need not, swamp the real Wicksell effect. It is essential for this swamping to occur at a single interest rate that the technology be continuous. Pierangelo Garegnani, Heinz D. Kurz & Neri Salvadori, and Saverio M. Fratini have examples that illustrate some possibilities with a continuum of techniques.

Row E is the case of Samuelson's Surrogate Production Function. Price Wicksell effects are zero when the factor price curve for a given technique is a straight line. The question mark after the label for Row F reflects my belief that this row catalogs an impossibility. If factor price curves are straight lines along their entire length, capital-reversing cannot arise.

Rows G, H, and I are cases in which the real Wicksell effect is zero. The real Wicksell effect is zero in the discrete case when the factor price curves are tangent at a switch point. I'm not sure how this extends to the continuous case, in which all points along the factor price frontier are non-switching points. If the Row I case is possible, the technique is not determined by the location of the corresponding factor price curve. I think this may be so for non-straight line factor price curves, but I'm unsure about this case.

These remarks suggest a research program. First, demonstrate that no possibilities exist that are not listed in Table 1. This would seem to be obvious. But I don't understand Andreu Mas-Colell's paper "Capital Theory Paradoxes: Anything Goes" (in Joan Robinson and Modern Economic Theory (ed. by G. Feiwel) (1989)). He shows some multi-valued relations where I would expect functions. Second, for those rows that are impossible in Table 1, demonstrate this impossibility. Third, for each possible row, construct a numeric example. For rows B and C, one should construct at least two examples, one for each direction of the capital market response. I suppose a third example, in which price and real Wicksell effects are exactly matched in magnitude would be amusing. Much of this research would be non-original; many components are in the literature.

Sunday, November 22, 2009

Nietzsche On The Individual As A Society

I have previously noted the problems for utility theory created by the application of Arrow's impossibility theorem to a single individual. And I had quoted a number of classic authors who wrote of themselves as being composed of more than one mind. Here's another:
"'Freedom of the will' - that is the expression for the complex state of delight of the person exercising volition, who commands and at the same time identifies himself with the executor of the order - who, as such, enjoys also the triumph over obstacles, but thinks within himself that it was really his will itself that overcame them. In this way the person exercising volition adds the feelings of delight of his successful executive instruments, the useful 'underwills' or undersouls - indeed our body is but a social structure composed of many souls - to his feelings of delight as commander. L'effet c'est moi. What happens here is what happens in every well-constructed and happy commonwealth; namely, the governing class identifies itself with the successes of the commonwealth. In all willing it is absolutely a question of commanding and obeying, on the basis, as already said, of a social structure composed of many 'souls'." -- Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future (Kaufmann translation), paragraph 19
By the way, the idea of modeling an individual choice with a structure underlying the textbook treatment of preferences over the elements of a linear space of commodities is not necessarily non-mainstream. I cannot say I know much about the relevant literature. However, I stumbled over an example - a paper, "Multiple Temptations", from John E. Stovall, a graduate student at the University of Rochester.

Wednesday, November 18, 2009

An Indeterminate Two-Person Zero-Sum Game With Perfect Information

1.0 Introduction
I have stumbled upon some odd mathematics, some mathematics that I have not validated. Consider the claim that all two-person zero-sum games with perfect information have a value. Apparently, this claim is inconsistent with the Axiom of Choice, an axiom in set theory. This inconsistency is shown by the Banach-Mazur game and its variants. I guess it is essential to this demonstration that these games have a potentially countable infinite number of moves.

I don't know that this demonstration is as important for economics as, for instance, W. F. Lucas' example of a cooperative game without an equilibrium.

A game has perfect information if the results of all moves prior to any given move are known to all players. Simple examples of games with imperfect information are card games in which the deal gives a player a hand which only he knows. A two-person zero-sum game is determinate if one can prove either (1) the first player wins some definite amount, (2) the second player wins some definite amount, or (3) the game is a draw. Chess is a determinate game, although it is in practice impossible to expand the tree enough to determine its value.

2.0 A Game
I steal this example from a Usenet post by Herman Rubin.

The game is fully specified by the rules and by defining a set C, where C is a given subset of the real numbers between 0 and 1, inclusive. The two players alternatively select the successive binary digits of the base-two expansion of a number within the interval [0, 1].

In other words, consider the number:

(1/2) x1 + (1/4) x2 + (1/8) x3 + (1/16) x4 + ...
where, for all i, xi is in {0, 1}. The first player chooses the binary digits with the odd indices, and the second player chooses the binary digits with the even indices. But they take turns and go in order.

The game ends with the second player paying the first player a unit when it is guaranteed that any further expansion will result in a number within C. The game ends with the second player winning a unit payment from the first player when it is guaranteed that any further expansion will result in a number in the complement of C.

A simple example is C = [0.5, 1]. The first player wins in this case. A more complicated game arises when C is the set of all irrational numbers in the unit interval. I gather this game is determinate, but I don't see offhand who wins. Finally, consider a set C that does not have a Lebesque measure. (The Axiom of Choice is necessary for the definition of such a set.) I gather that in this case, the game is not determinate. Nobody can tell a priori who will win.

Sunday, November 15, 2009

Lee Boldeman's Critique From Australia

Lee Boldeman's book, The Cult of the Market: Economic Fundamentalism and its Discontents is available in PDF. Boldeman does report some internal critiques of orthodox economics, such as Lipsey and Lancaster's theory of the second best. But, without having read the whole book yet, his perspective seems to be more about emphasizing an external critique of methodological individualism. Individuals are embedded in society. Boldeman says he wrote his book because he didn't know of another that covered what he wanted to say. I think his approach parallels Stephen Marglin's The Dismal Science: How Thinking Like an Economist Undermines Community. If Boldeman had read Marglin, he might still have wanted to write, since Marglin doesn't address the context of Australian public policy. Catholics in classes taught by the soon-to-be-gone department at Notre Dame would probably find Boldeman's book at interest.

Thursday, November 12, 2009

"And A Whole Generation Were Butchered And Damned"

"I spent the evening walking around the streets, especially in the neighborhood of Trafalgar Square, noticing cheering crowds and making myself sensitive to the emotions of passers-by. During this and the following days, I discovered to my amazement that average men and women were delighted at the prospect of war. I had fondly imagined what most pacifists contended, that wars were forced upon a reluctant population by despotic and Machiavellian governments. I had noticed during previous years how carefully Sir Edward Grey lied in order to prevent the public from knowing the methods by which he was committing us to the support of France in the event of war. I naively imagined that when the public discovered how he had lied to them, they would be annoyed; instead of which, they were grateful to him for having spared them the moral responsibility." -- Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell: The Middle Years: 1914-1944

Monday, November 09, 2009

Back Issues of Methodus Available On-Line

I've just discovered the International Network for Economic Method (INEM). They publish the Journal of Economic Methodology. This journal replaced Methodus, INEM's bulletin. Back issues of Methodus are freely available. I've barely begun sampling what's here - for example, a 1992 Geoff Harcourt comment on political economy or a 1991 Kevin Hoover review of Mirowski's More Heat Than Light.

Friday, November 06, 2009

Error Built Upon Error

This inspired the picture below. Of course, I have more in soft-copy.
My Dead Tree Austrian Library

Sunday, November 01, 2009

Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen

I find Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen an intriguing economist. He discovered the non-substitution theorem and, apparently, the Hawkins-Simon condition.

Georgescu-Roegen developed a critique of neoclassical production functions. He argued that it applied to Leontief input-output theory too. This critique relies on distinctions among fund, flow, stock, and service. Funds are unchanged in the production process, while flows are altered. A stock is a productive input that can be used to generate flows at any rate, while a fund can generate services up to some maximum rate. In Sraffa's approach, land, I guess, is modeled as a fund. In artisan production, funds are idle most of the time, while a factory keeps their funds in use by having many laborers work slightly out of parallel. Georgescu-Roegen argued that production functions should be replaced with functionals, in which the arguments show the use of factors as functions of time.

Georgescu-Roegen accused other economists, such as Robert Solow, of ignoring the increased entropy that production causes. Usable mineral resources are finite. Georgescu-Roegen formulated what he called the fourth law of thermodynamics, which says that available matter decreases. Waste products become scattered and unusable.

He also made a distinction between what he called arithmomorphic and dialectic concepts. Arithmomorphic concepts are suitable for mathematical reasoning. Dialetic concepts are distinct but overlapping, and they are suitable for qualitative reasoning, as appropriate for a good understanding of economic development.

Georgescu-Roegen's analysis included a system of energy accounting, without accepting an energy theory of value. As forerunners, he mentions, for example, Frederick Soddy. (Soddy, apparently a Nobel laureate for discovering the existence of isotopes, called his economic philosophy ergosophy.)

Georgescu-Roegen's policy conclusions focused on converting socities to ones in which their economies were sustainable, with a concomitant smaller population in what are now considered advanced countries.

I don't think I've done justice to the subtlety and insightfulness of Georgescu-Roegen's contributions to economics with these scattered observations.

References
  • Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen (1986) "Man and Production", in Foundations of Economics: Structures of Inquiry and Economic Theory (Ed. by M. Baranzini and R. Scazzieri) Basil Blackwell
  • John Gowdy and Susan Mesner (1998) "The Evolution of Georgescu-Roegen's Bioeconomics" Review of Social Economy, V. 56, N. 2 (Summer)
  • Eberhard K. Seifert (1994) "Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas", in The Elgar Companion to Institutional and Evolutionary Economics (Ed. by G. M. Hodgson, W. J. Samuels, and M. R. Tool), Edward Elgar

Friday, October 30, 2009

A Neoricardian Model of International Trade

Hoisted from comments of October 28:
"Your interest has much in common with my research field. I am a Sraffian and works in the field of international trade theory.

You have cited several times Steedman and Metcalfe. They have worked on the open small country case. As a trade theory, this is not general enough. It cannot analyse the South-North problem, to cite an obvious example. The Ricardian trade theory should be extended to the many country case with the traded commodities across countries. As Sraffa named his major work Productions of commodities by means of commodities, the production is circular in its character and cannot be arranged linearly as it is assumed in the Austrian tradition. Heckscher-Ohlin theory also assumes this linearity, starting with the endowed production factors, then sometimes intermediates goods and final goods. This is completely inadequate as production structure. But the task to develop a trade theory with this circular structure is quite hard. Steedman and Metcalfe did not succeed in this attempt. I recently found the method how to overcome this difficulty. Please look into my paper: A New Construction of Ricardian Trade Theory—A Many-country, Many-commodity Case with Intermediate Goods and Choice of Production Techniques" -- Yoyo_the_economist
I have not had a chance to read this paper. Based on the claims in the introduction, it does sound quite intriguing.

Monday, October 26, 2009

Energy Return On Energy Investment (EROEI)?

According to this New York Times article:
"Last week, about 50 scholars in economics, ecology, engineering and other fields met at the State University of New York's College of Environmental Science and Forestry for their second annual conference on biophysical economics. The new field shares features with ecological economics, a much more established discipline with conferences boasting hundreds of attendees...

...Central to their argument is an understanding that the survival of all living creatures is limited by the concept of energy return on investment (EROI): that any living thing or living societies can survive only so long as they are capable of getting more net energy from any activity than they expend during the performance of that activity.

For instance, if a squirrel burns energy eating nuts, those nuts had better give the squirrel more energy back then it expended, or the squirrel will inevitably die. It is a rule that lies at the core of studying animal and plant behavior, and human society should be looked at no differently, as even technologically complex societies are still governed by EROI...

...Through analyzing historical production data, experts say the petroleum sector's EROI in this country was about 100-to-1 in 1930, meaning one had to burn approximately 1 barrel of oil's worth of energy to get 100 barrels out of the ground. By the 1990s, it is thought, that number slid to less than 36-to-1, and further down to 19-to-1 by 2006..."

I haven't looked up how these scholars calculate EROEI. But it seems to me that an approximate value for EROEI is easily found from Leontief Input-Output tables, as available in, for example, the United States National Income and Product Accounts (NIPA). Consider the reciprocals, expressed as percentages, of the diagonal elements of the Leontief inverse, (I - A)-1. The NIPA express the entries in Leontief matrices in dollar terms, not the physical terms I prefer for theory. But since these percentages are pure numbers, calculated as ratios, this makes no difference.

I gather the EROEI is approximately this reciprocal for the petroleum sector. In the North American Industry Classification System (NAICS), the sector of concern is industry code 211, "Oil and Gas Extraction".

A better approximation would account for the energy embodied in the other inputs in the vertically integrated oil and gas extraction industry, that is, the corresponding column of the Leontief inverse. An even better approximation would include some concern for depreciation of fixed capital.

Saturday, October 24, 2009

On Some Rightists

Alex, the Yorkshire Ranter had some comments about "libertarians", that is, propertarians. (I've previously mentioned Alan Haworth, another Britisher I find amusing on that topic.)

I've wondered about Gavin Kennedy. I agree that it's bad history to claim Adam Smith's metaphor of the invisible hand is about allocative efficiency and clarified by the first welfare theorem. Consider:
"Yet the project of appropriating the politics of the Wealth of Nations to the consideration of the present has not lost its attractions... Examples of this proliferate. One has only to look to ...Gavin Kennedy (2005, a former Scottish Nationalist Party economics spokesperson)..." -- Murray Milgate & Shannon C. Stimson (2009) After Adam Smith: A Century of Transformation in Politics and Political Economy, Princeton University Press.

Wednesday, October 21, 2009

Ken Kesey Poster

Reading a Book
I bought the poster a bit over ten years ago. As I understand, Kesey's farm outside Eugene, Oregon, makes the label below appropriate.

Saturday, October 17, 2009

Heterodox Economics Movements I Don't Pay Much Attention To

As I understand it, each of the following had advocates around the globe in the first half of the twentieth century:
  • Georgism (I have read Progress & Poverty)
  • Silvio Gesell (Mentioned by Keynes in Chapter 23 of the General Theory)
  • Social credit (Keynes also mentions Major Douglas in Chapter 23 of the General Theory)
  • Technocracy
I gather remnants of their advocate organizations still exist. But I gather they have little representation among academic economists.

Sunday, October 11, 2009

Unemployment In A Barter Economy

"...it may be doubted whether under a system of barter the decisions of individuals would have their full effects..." - Piero Sraffa (1932)
In the General Theory, Keynes presents an argument for how widespread unemployment can come about. I think money enters in an essential way in Keynes' argument. This raises the question whether unemployment would exist if it were not for monetary phenomena.

Sraffa, in Production of Commodites by Means of Commodities, has a lot to say about numeraires, including the Standard Commodity. One can read Sraffa as making certain points about a monetary economy.

But put that reading of Sraffa aside. Instead, think of Sraffa's model as half of a limit point of a neoclassical model of general equilibrium. The other half of such a model of a steady state consists of utility maximization. This is a model of a barter economy. And steady state models can exhibit multiple equilibria, bifurcations, and catastrophes. I think these phenomena suggest the possibility of complex dynamics. Thus, even though neither general overproduction nor an uncleared labor market can arise in a long run competitive equilibrium in a barter economy, such an equilibrium may never be reached. Instead, the economy may cycle around with unemployment continually being recreated.

The idea that unemployment could be cured by making labor and product markets more flexibile is unsupported by price theory.

Thursday, October 08, 2009

Endogenous Money Supply In The Long Run

This post is not about how the United States Federal Reserve cannot control, on a day-to-day basis, the quantity of money in circulation. Rather, I consider financial innovation over time leads to the creation of new debt instruments that fall under a reasonable definition of "money".

One way of looking at money is that, under capitalism, money buys goods, and goods sell for money, but goods do not buy goods. A simple example: I understand one can write checks against a hedge fund. So hedge funds are money.

The emergence of new forms of money illustrates why no final systems of regulations can exist in a capitalist economy. Should something like the Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation be set up to guarantee these new forms of money? If so, some capital requirements, restrictions on leverage ratios, and so on would need to be instituted. Maybe some sort of firewalls, as in the Glass-Steagall act, should be rebuilt.

Sunday, October 04, 2009

Friday, October 02, 2009

Enrico Barone, The Originator Of The Socialist Calculation Argument

Arguably, socialism, when implemented with a centrally planned economy, is guaranteed to not produce a fairly high standard of living. Market prices are needed. This argument was originated by Enrico Barone:
"25. But it is frankly inconceivable that the economic determination of the technical coefficients can be made a priori, in such a way as to satisfy the condition of the minimum cost of production which is an essential condition for obtaining that maximum to which we have referred. The economic variability of the technical coefficients is certainly neglected by the collectivists; but that it is one of the most important sides of the question Pareto has already very clearly shown in one of his many ingenious contributions to the science.

The determination of the coefficients economically most advantageous can only be done in an experimental way: and not on a small scale, as could be done in a laboratory, but with experiments on a very large scale, because often the advantage of the variation has its origin precisely in a new and greater dimension of the undertaking. Experiments may be successful in the sense that they may lead to a lower cost combination of factors; or they may be unsuccessful, in which case that particular organization may not be copied and repeated and others will be preferred, which experimentally have given a better result.

The Ministry of Production could not do without these experiments for the determination of the economically most advantageous technical if it would realize the condition of the minimum cost of production which is essential for the attainment of the maximum collective welfare.

It is on this account that the equations of the equilibrium with the maximum collective welfare are not soluble a priori, on paper.

26. Some collectivist writers, bewailing the continual destruction of firms (those with higher costs) by free competition, think that the creation of enterprises to be destroyed later can be avoided and hope that with organized production it is possible to avoid the dissipation and destruction of wealth which such experiments involve, and which they believe to be the peculiar property of 'anarchist' production. Thereby these writers simply show that they have no clear idea of what production really is, and that they are not even disposed to probe a little deeper into the problem which will concern the Ministry which will be established for the purpose in the Collectivist State.

We repeat, that if the Ministry will not remain bound by the traditional technical coefficients, which would produce a destruction of wealth in another sense - in the sense that the greater wealth which could have been realized will not be realized - it has no other means of determining a priori the technical coefficients most advantageous economically, and must of necessity resort to experiments on a large scale in order to decide afterwards which are the most appropriate organizations, which it is advantageous to maintain in existence and to enlarge to obtain the collective maximum more easily, and which, on the other hand, it is best to discard as failures.

27. Conclusions. From what we have seen and demonstrated hitherto, it is obvious how fantastic those doctrines are which imagine that the production in the collectivist regime would be ordered in a manner substantially different from that of 'anarchist' production.

If the Ministry of Production proposes to obtain the collective maximum - which it obviously must, whatever law of distribution may be adopted - all the economic categories of the old regime must reappear, though maybe with other names: prices, salaries, interest, rent, profit, saving, etc..." -- Enrico Barone, translated from "The Ministry of Production in the Collectivist State" Giornale delgi Economisti (1908)