Monday, July 15, 2024

Is The Labor Theory Of Value Compatible With Automation?

Automation Of Chinese Ports

With automation, many processes for production and distribution now execute with minimal human oversight. How can the labor theory of value, as in volume 1 of Capital, be compatible with this?

Marx has some comments on this subject in the Grundrisse:

The exchange of living labour for objectified labour – i.e. the positing of social labour in the form of the contradiction of capital and wage labour – is the ultimate development of the value-relation and of production resting on value. Its presupposition is – and remains – the mass of direct labour time, the quantity of labour employed, as the determinant factor in the production of wealth. But to the degree that large industry develops, the creation of real wealth comes to depend less on labour time and on the amount of labour employed than on the power of the agencies set in motion during labour time, whose 'powerful effectiveness' is itself in turn out of all proportion to the direct labour time spent on their production, but depends rather on the general state of science and on the progress of technology, or the application of this science to production. (The development of this science, especially natural science, and all others with the latter, is itself in turn related to the development of material production.) Agriculture, e.g., becomes merely the application of the science of material metabolism, its regulation for the greatest advantage of the entire body of society.

Real wealth manifests itself, rather – and large industry reveals this – in the monstrous disproportion between the labour time applied, and its product, as well as in the qualitative imbalance between labour, reduced to a pure abstraction, and the power of the production process it superintends. Labour no longer appears so much to be included within the production process; rather, the human being comes to relate more as watchman and regulator to the production process itself. (What holds for machinery holds likewise for the combination of human activities and the development of human intercourse.)

No longer does the worker insert a modified natural thing as middle link between the object and himself; rather, he inserts the process of nature, transformed into an industrial process, as a means between himself and inorganic nature, mastering it. He steps to the side of the production process instead of being its chief actor. In this transformation, it is neither the direct human labour he himself performs, nor the time during which he works, but rather the appropriation of his own general productive power, his understanding of nature and his mastery over it by virtue of his presence as a social body – it is, in a word, the development of the social individual which appears as the great foundation-stone of production and of wealth. The theft of alien labour time, on which the present wealth is based, appears a miserable foundation in face of this new one, created by large-scale industry itself. As soon as labour in the direct form has ceased to be the great well-spring of wealth, labour time ceases and must cease to be its measure, and hence exchange value [must cease to be the measure] of use value. The surplus labour of the mass has ceased to be the condition for the development of general wealth, just as the non-labour of the few, for the development of the general powers of the human head. With that, production based on exchange value breaks down, and the direct, material production process is stripped of the form of penury and antithesis. The free development of individualities, and hence not the reduction of necessary labour time so as to posit surplus labour, but rather the general reduction of the necessary labour of society to a minimum, which then corresponds to the artistic, scientific etc. development of the individuals in the time set free, and with the means created, for all of them.

Capital itself is the moving contradiction, [in] that it presses to reduce labour time to a minimum, while it posits labour time, on the other side, as sole measure and source of wealth. Hence it diminishes labour time in the necessary form so as to increase it in the superfluous form; hence posits the superfluous in growing measure as a condition – question of life or death – for the necessary. On the one side, then, it calls to life all the powers of science and of nature, as of social combination and of social intercourse, in order to make the creation of wealth independent (relatively) of the labour time employed on it. On the other side, it wants to use labour time as the measuring rod for the giant social forces thereby created, and to confine them within the limits required to maintain the already created value as value. Forces of production and social relations – two different sides of the development of the social individual – appear to capital as mere means, and are merely means for it to produce on its limited foundation. In fact, however, they are the material conditions to blow this foundation sky-high. 'Truly wealthy a nation, when the working day is 6 rather than 12 hours. Wealth is not command over surplus labour time' (real wealth), 'but rather, disposable time outside that needed in direct production, for every individual and the whole society.' (The Source and Remedy etc. 1821, p. 6.)

Nature builds no machines, no locomotives, railways, electric telegraphs, self-acting mules etc. These are products of human industry; natural material transformed into organs of the human will over nature, or of human participation in nature. They are organs of the human brain, created by the human hand; the power of knowledge, objectified.

The development of fixed capital indicates to what degree general social knowledge has become a direct force of production, and to what degree, hence, the conditions of the process of social life itself have come under the control of the general intellect and been transformed in accordance with it. To what degree the powers of social production have been produced, not only in the form of knowledge, but also as immediate organs of social practice, of the real life process. -- Karl Marx, Grundrisse, Contradiction between the foundation of bourgeois production (value as measure) and its development. Machines etc.

I take the paragraphing above from David McLellan's severely abridged version. I think I need a hard-copy version if I am ever going to fully read the Grundrisse. For what it is worth, John Von Neumann has a theory of value for a fully automated economy.

Marx above seems to offer one story of how capitalism will end. An issue exists with finding supposed anti-Marxist arguments echoed in writings unpublished in Marx's lifetime. It is not clear how to working class has a role in the above story. Is this story consistent with what Marx says in Capital, as quoted in Section 4 here? Sundry observations do not neccessarily add up to a consistent theory.

5 comments:

Blissex said...

«many processes for production and distribution now execute with minimal human oversight. How can the labor theory of value, as in volume 1 of Capital, be compatible with this?»

Ah there is here a very important detail that is often forgotten and yet explains a lot of the approach of that guy: he very explicitly says that the work of slaves or animals (and machines too of course) produces no "value", only the work of free workers produces "value".

Very important side note: as our blogger has quoted in the past, Marx also writes explicitly that usefulness (as opposed to "value" can come from "nature", not just labor, or the labor of free workers.

This is a critical point: his "theory of value" is not as theory of labor as "value", but cost accounting solely of "value" *defined* as labor as a commodity (more precisely "labor-power"), not labor in general. Since the labor of slaves or animals (or machines) is not a commodity as it is not sold and purchased in the markets, then *by definition* it cannot produce any "value",

That is different from the theory of value of what we call "the classics" was based on the argument that all useful things and their prerequisites are the result of labor ("nature" for the physiocrats), so probably for "economic goods [and services]" (and only for them) prices would converge to be proportional to total labor content, given competition.

The aim of the "classics" was to understand the political (as opposed to the "domestic") economy as both a production system and a consumption system, with prices as the link, and the concepts being usefulness and work (in general, not just that of free workers): as a rule economic goods less useful than the work needed to make them would not be made (their plus-value being negative), prices would be pushed by competition towards the work content, and consumer surplus would be the difference between usefulness and price, and rent that between the competitive price and the actual price.

Very important side node: the same political economists with the same aim today would not argue that "all useful things and their prerequisites are made with labor", but with *energy*, of which labor is just a special case of things that can produce "work".

But I reckon that the goal of Marx is not so much to understand production, prices, consumption, but to understand the distribution of plus-value among market participants in a "capitalist" system where labor-power is a commodity, and therefore he *defines* "value" as solely the labor of free workers, those who are free to sell their labor-power in the markets (slaves, animals, machines, "nature" not being market participants). As I keep saying, I think that he has not expressed a *theory* of value, and I reckon he was not very interested in that.

Blissex said...

«Marx has some comments on this subject in the Grundrisse:»

Interesting quote indeed. From my point of view that is a description of a system in which the distribution of plus-value no longer matters because there is so much of it, that is the industrial system has become a very bountiful "nature".

the creation of real wealth comes to depend less on labour time and on the amount of labour employed than on the power of the agencies set in motion during labour time

Here “real wealth” seems to me to mean "usefulness" (I am reluctant to use "utility" or even "ofelimity" in this context), and the “the power of the agencies” is "energy" (in our modern understanding, even if some people still think that is “the general state of science and on the progress of technology” like Marx seemed to do as well).

Consider the "domestic economy" case of someone living on a farm with a workshop with a loom and tools and having four slaves to work the fields and loom and workshop: in marxian cost accounting there is no "exploitation", because there is no selling and buying of labor power. Only the labor of the owner produces "value" (again *by definition*), and the owner is self-employed, so he owns all plus-value, does not have to cede part of it to an employer in market transaction. Exactly the same in the case of four androids instead of four slaves, or four machines, or four trained animals.

The four slaves, androids, machines, trained animals turn fuel (food, electricity, petrol, ...) into "energy" and then into "work", just like "nature" (e.g. sunlight into apples) or a free worker would.

That is simply not a case to which the marxian *definition* of "value" as the labor of free workers in a market system is meant to apply, which I think is pretty much what Marx also says in the quote.

Consider then the case of a "political economy" composed exclusively of many slaves (or androids or trained animals or machines) and many fewer owners: that is also the case described in the quote above. There is no "exploitation" as all free workers are self-employed, and they trade the products of their free labor in the markets as commodities, but no labor ("labor power") is traded in those markets, and there is such abundance of “the agencies set in motion during labour time” (the work, which is not "labor", of slaves or androids etc.) that the self-employed workers enjoy the “'Truly wealthy a nation, when the working day is 6 rather than 12 hours. [...]'” situation.

Blissex said...

«the work, which is not "labor"»

This is a critical "terms-of-art" point: in common english (and probably in common german too) "labor" is an old-fashioned synonym of "work", and "value" is an old-fashioned synonym of "usefulness". But I reckon that in marxian technical terminology that is not the case: "value" is *defined* as "labor" which is *defined* as "work of free people". These definition as I keep saying have an interesting (but narrow) purpose, but they are somewhat surprising and can lead to misunderstandings.

In a wider sense "usefulness" is a potential consequence of "work" and "work" can be done by nature, people, animal, machines, etc. thanks to "energy" supplied by "fuels" (sunlight, hay, food, coal, oil, ...), and "consumer surplus" is a very important concept as to "wealth".

sturai said...

I like to think about the future of capitalism and automation following the work of Luigi Pasinetti. Specifically with the Cambridge Equation with special emphasis on the anti-dual or anti-anti-pasinettian case.

https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Luca-Zamparelli/publication/310513647_Wealth_Distribution_Elasticity_of_Substitution_and_Piketty_An_%27Anti-Dual%27_Pasinetti_Economy/links/59e14972aca2724cbfdb7603/Wealth-Distribution-Elasticity-of-Substitution-and-Piketty-An-Anti-Dual-Pasinetti-Economy.pdf

https://wps-feb.ugent.be/Papers/wp_23_1064.pdf

Extra:

https://www.econstor.eu/bitstream/10419/168156/1/VfS-2017-pid-2791.pdf

Robert Vienneau said...

Blissez, I am not sure I agree. But I tend to think of labor values as calculated with a time of accounting.

I just quickly skimmed those papers. Stiglitz sometimes seems very much a Post-Keynesian. And he learned the theory at Cambridge.