This is another example of Engels explaining the theory of historical materialism.
I know of this letter from Mills and Goldstick (1989). They also point
out this letter from Engels.
Here we see the metaphor of ideas "standing on their head", not in relation to Hegel's idealism,
but as real economic relations reflected in finance.
I like the emphasis on the interdependence of industries that could be expressed in Leontief matrices.
Does this letter express a deterministic, strict dependence of the superstructure on the base?
Or does Engels explain historical materialism as a mutual interaction of base and superstructure?
London, 27 October 1890
Dear Schmidt,
I am taking advantage of this, the first free time I have had, to answer
you letter. I think you would be very well advised to accept the
post in Zurich. At any rate you'll be able to learn a good deal about
economics there, especially if you bear in mind that Zurich is, after all,
only a third-rate financial and speculative market and hence that the
impressions to be gained there will be dulled, if not deliberately distorted,
these being but reflections seen at second or third remove. But
you will learn how the machinery works in practice and will be obliged
to follow at first hand the stock market reports from London,
New York, Paris, Berlin and Vienna, and thus the world market - in
its reflection as a money and stock market - will be revealed to you.
Economics, politics, etc., are reflected as objects are in the human
eye - they pass through a converging lens and are therefore seen the
wrong way up, standing on their heads. Except that there is no
nervous apparatus to set them on their feet again for the benefit of the
imagination. Your money market man sees the trend of industry and
of the world market merely in the inverted reflection of the money
and stock markets and thus for him effect becomes cause. I observed
this back in the 40s in Manchester; as a guide to industrial progress
and its periodical peaks and troughs, the London stock market reports
were absolutely useless, since the gentlemen sought to explain
everything in terms of money market crises, though these were themselves
for the most part little more than symptoms. At that time they
were concerned to explain away industrial crises by attributing them
to temporary overproduction and thus the thing also had a tendentious
aspect which invited distortion. This is a point which has now
ceased to apply - once and for all, at any rate so far as we are concerned,
and it is, moreover, a fact that the money market may also have
its own crises in which actual industrial disturbances play only a subordinate
role, if any at all, and in this sphere there is much to be ascertained
and investigated, particularly in regard to the history of
the last 20 years.
Where there is division of labour on a social scale, the various sections
become mutually independent. Production is, in the final analysis,
the decisive factor. But as soon as trade in products becomes independent
of actual production, the former follows a trend of its own
which is, by and large, undoubtedly dictated by production but, in
specific cases and within the framework of that general dependence,
does in turn obey laws of its own, laws inherent in the nature of this
new factor; it is a trend having its own phases and reacting in turn on
the trend of production. The discovery of America was due to the
gold famine which had already driven the Portuguese to Africa (cf.
Soetbeer's Edelmetall-Produktion), because the vast expansion of
European industry and the corresponding growth in trade in the 14th
and 15th centuries called for more means of exchange than Germany - the main source of silver from 1450 to 1550 - was able to provide.
The conquest of India by the Portuguese, Dutch and British between
1500 and 1800 had as its aim import from India and no one
thought of sending exports there. And yet how tremendous were the
repercussions upon industry of these discoveries and conquests carried
out solely in the interests of trade - it was only the need to export
to those countries which created and developed large-scale industry.
It is the same with the money market. Once trade in money becomes
divorced from trade in commodities, it will - under certain circumstances
determined by production and by the trade in commodities and within those limits — develop in its own way subject to the
special laws and distinctive phases determined by its own nature. If,
in addition and in the course of this further development, the trade in
money expands to comprise trade in securities, the said securities being
not simply government paper, but also the shares of industrial
and commercial concerns, i.e. if the trade in money gains direct control
of a section of the production by which it is largely dominated,
then the reaction of the trade in money on production will be even
stronger and more complex. The traders in money own railways,
mines, foundries, etc. These means of production assume a twofold aspect:
They must be run, now in accordance with the immediate interests
of production, now in accordance with the needs of the shareholders
in so far as these are traders in money. The most striking example
of this is the North American railroads, the running of which is
entirely dependent on the day-to-day stock market operations of
a Jay Gould, Vanderbilt, etc., which have nothing whatever to do
with any particular railroad or its interests quaa means of transport.
And even here in England the railway companies have for decades
been fighting over the boundary areas separating this concern or
that - struggles in which a vast amount of money has been squandered,
not in the interests of production and transport, but solely out of
a rivalry which for the most part had but one purpose, namely to facilitate
the stock market operations of the traders in money who held
the shares.
With these few remarks about my view of the relationship of production
to the trade in commodities and of both to the trade in
money, I have already dealt in the main with your questions about
historical materialism generally. The subject is best approached
from the standpoint of the division of labour. Society engenders certain
common functions which it cannot do without. Those nominated
for this purpose form a new branch of the division of labour within society.
They thereby acquire interests of their own vis-à-vis, amongst
others, their mandatories and become independent of them - and so
you have the state. From then on the process is much the same as in
the trade in commodities and, later, the trade in money - while the
new independent power must, it is true, generally follow the trend of
production, it will also, by virtue of its inherent independence, i.e.
a relative independence formerly conferred upon it and which it has
gradually enlarged, react in turn upon the conditions and the course
of production. It is the interaction of two unequal forces, of the economic
trend on the one hand and the new political power which is
striving for the greatest possible independence and which, having
once been installed, assumes a trend of its own, on the other. By and
large, the economic trend will predominate but it must also be reacted
upon by the political trend which it has itself induced and which has
been endowed with relative independence - the trend of, on the one
hand, state power and, on the other, of the simultaneously engendered
opposition. Just as the trend of the industrial market is largely
reflected in the money market, given the provisos set out above, but,
of course, the wrong way up, the struggle between the already extant
and warring classes is reflected in the struggle between government
and opposition, and again the wrong way up; it is no longer reflected
directly but indirectly, not as a class struggle but as a struggle over
political principles, and in so distorted a form that it has taken us
a thousand years to sort it out again.
The government may react to economic developments in three
ways: it can take the same direction, in which case things go faster; it
may take a contrary one, in which case, as conditions are today and
in any of the larger nations, it will eventually come to grief, or it may
block certain lines of economic development and lay down others - which will ultimately amount to the same as one of the two foregoing
instances. But it is obvious that, in instances 2 and 3, political power
can wreak havoc with economic development and cause energy and
materials to be squandered on a vast scale.
Then again there is the instance of the seizure and brutal destruction
of economic resources which, in earlier days and in certain circumstances,
could ruin economic development both locally and nationally.
Today, this would mostly have the opposite effect, at least
where the larger nations are concerned. In the long run the vanquished
may have more to gain economically, politically and morally
than, on occasion, the victor.
It is much the same in the case of the law: As soon as the new division
of labour becomes necessary and creates professional lawyers, yet
another new, independent field is opened up which, for all its general
dependence on production and trade, is nevertheless capable of reacting
in its own way to those spheres. In a modern state not only must
the law correspond to the general economic situation and be its expression,
it must of itself constitute a coherent expression that does not,
by reason of internal contradictions, give itself the lie. And to achieve
this, the fidelity with which economic conditions are reflected is increasingly
thrown to the winds. All the more so for the rarity with
which a statute book is the harsh, unmitigated, unadulterated expression
of the domination of one class: this of itself would be contrary to
the 'concept of law'. The pure, logical concept of law of the revolutionary
bourgeoisie of 1792-96 had already been adulterated in many
respects even in the Code Napoléon and, in so far as it was embodied
therein, has had to be constantly subjected to all manner of
modifications as a result of the growing power of the proletariat. Not
that this has prevented the Code Napoléon from being the statute
book on which all new codifications in every part of the world are
based. Thus the course of the 'law's development' has largely consisted
simply in this: Firstly, the attempt to eliminate the contradictions
arising from the direct translation of economic conditions into legal
principles and to establish an harmonious legal system and, secondly,
the fact that the influence and pressure of further economic developments
repeatedly disrupt that system, involving it in fresh contradictions
(at this stage I am speaking only of civil law).
The reflection of economic conditions as legal principles is likewise
necessarily one that presents the image the wrong way up; it does so
without the beholder being aware of it; the lawyer imagines he is
dealing in a priori principles whereas they are, in fact, no more than
economic reflections - and thus the whole thing is the wrong way up.
And it seems to me self-evident that this inversion which, in as much
as it is not recognised, constitutes what we call an ideological view,
reacts in its turn on the economic base and may, within certain limits,
modify the same. The basis of the law of inheritance, assuming the
family to have attained the same stage of development, is an economic
one. Nevertheless, it would be difficult to prove that, for instance, absolute
testamentary freedom in England and the strict limits imposed
thereon in France are in every respect of economic origin. But both,
in a very significant way, react on the economy in that they influence
the distribution of wealth.
Now as regards the more rarefied ideological fields such as religion,
philosophy, etc.; these have a prehistorical fund of what today would
be termed rubbish which was taken over lock, stock and barrel by the
historical period. In so far as these various false conceptions of nature,
of the nature of man, of spirits, magic forces, etc., are economically
based, it is only in a negative sense; false conceptions of nature are the
corollary of the low level of economic development in the prehistorical
period, but also on occasion its precondition if not its actual cause.
And even if economic necessity may have provided the main incentive
for progress in natural science and done so to an increasing extent,
it would be pedantic to seek economic causes for all this primitive
rubbish. The history of science is the history of the gradual elimination
of that rubbish and/or its replacement by new, if progressively
less ridiculous, rubbish. The people responsible for this in turn belong
to special spheres of the division of labour and see themselves as working
in an independent field. And to the extent that they constitute an
independent group within the social division of labour, what they
produce, including their errors, exerts a reciprocal influence on social
development as a whole and even on economic development. But for
all that, they are themselves in their turn subject to the dominant influence
of economic development. In philosophy, for example, this is
most easily demonstrated in respect of the bourgeois period. Hobbes
was the first modern materialist (in the 18th-century sense), but an
absolutist at a time when, throughout Europe, absolute monarchy
was in its heyday and, in England, was embarking on a struggle with
the populace. In religion as in politics, Locke was the product of the
class compromise of 1688. The English deists and their more logical
successors, the French materialists, were the true philosophers of
the bourgeoisie - and, in the case of the French, even of the bourgeois
revolution. German philosophy, from Kant to Hegel, is permeated
by the German philistine - now in a positive, now in a negative,
sense. But in every epoch philosophy, as a definite sphere of the division
of labour, presupposes a definite fund of ideas inherited from its
predecessors and from which it takes its departure. And that is why
economically backward countries can nevertheless play first fiddle
where philosophy is concerned - France in the 18th century as compared
with England, upon whose philosophy the French based themselves
and, later on, Germany as compared with both. But in France
as in Germany, philosophy, like the general flowering of literature at
that time, was also the result of growing economic prosperity. I am in
no doubt about the ultimate supremacy of economic development
over these fields also, but it will come about within the terms laid
down by each individual field; in philosophy, for instance, by the operation
of economic influences (which again for the most part operate
only in their political, etc., guise) on extant philosophical material
handed down by predecessors. Here, political economy creates nothing
a novo [from scratch], but determines the way in which the existing fund of ideas
changes and develops, and this too is done for the most part indirectly,
since it is its political, legal and moral reflections which exert
the greatest immediate influence on philosophy.
As for religion, I have said all that is necessary in the last chapter of
Feuerbach.
So if Barth opines that we deny that the political, etc., reflections of
the economic trend have any effect whatsoever on that trend itself, he
is simply tilting at windmills. After all, he only has to look at Marx's
Eighteenth Brumaire which is devoted almost exclusively to the particular
role played by political struggles and events - needless to say
within the framework of their general dependence on economic conditions.
Or again at Capital, e. g. the section on the working day
where legislation, which is, after all, a political act, appears in such an
uncompromising light. Or at the section on the history of the bourgeoisie
(Chapter 24). Otherwise why should we be fighting for
the political dictatorship of the proletariat if political power is
economically powerless? Might (i.e. state power) is also an
economic force!
But I have no time at present to criticise the book. The third
volume has got to come out first and in any case I believe that e.g.
Bernstein is also perfectly capable of attending to it.
What all these gentlemen lack is dialectics. All they ever see is
cause on the one hand and effect on the other. But what they fail to
see is that this is an empty abstraction, that in the real world such metaphysically
polar opposites exist only in a crisis, that instead the
whole great process takes place solely and entirely in the form of
interplay - if of very unequal forces of which the economic trend is by
far the strongest, the oldest and the most vital - and that here nothing
is absolute and everything relative. So far as they are concerned,
Hegel might never have existed.
As regards the rumpus in the party, I was forcibly dragged into it by
the gentlemen of the opposition and thus had no choice. Mr Ernst's
conduct vis-à-vis myself is quite indescribable unless I call it that of
a schoolboy. I am sorry if he's a sick man and forced to write for his
living. But if someone has an imagination so vivid that he can't read
a line without inferring the opposite of what it says, he should apply
his imagination to spheres other than socialism which is no figment.
He should write novels, plays, art criticism and the like, when all he
will harm is bourgeois culture, benefiting us in the process. He might
then acquire sufficient maturity to be able to achieve something in
our field also. Never before have I seen such a rigmarole of half-baked
material and utter rubbish as has been dished out by the said opposition.
And these callow lads, who are blind to everything but their
own boundless egotism, propose to dictate party tactics. I have learnt
more from a single one of Bebel's articles in the Vienna Arbeiter-Zeitung
than from all the rigmarole these chaps have produced. And
they imagine they are worth more than that clear-sighted man who
has such an admirably correct grasp of circumstances and depicts
them so graphically and succinctly. They are all of them failed belletrists,
and even a successful belletrist is a pretty obnoxious animal.
I should be sorry were the Volks-Tribüne to succumb. Under your
editorship it has shown that something might well be achieved by
a weekly which devotes more space to theory than to news - and
I am well aware what sort of contributors you have! But I must say
that, now that the Neue Zeit has become a weekly, it's somewhat
doubtful whether yours can be kept going. At all events, you will be
glad to cast off the joys and sorrows of editorship and have time for
something other than purely journalistic tasks. And even in Berlin the
immediate future will be dominated by all the various reverberations
of the late rumpus, and there'll be nothing to gain for anyone by being
mixed up in it.
Your printing the passage from my letter did no harm, but that
sort of thing is best avoided. In a letter, one writes from memory and
at speed, without looking anything up, etc., and is thus always liable
to let slip some expression which may well be seized on by one of those
people we Rhinelanders describe as a Korinthenscheisser [someone who trivializes everything], and God
knows what rubbish might not come of it.
Many thanks for your anticipatory congratulations on my 70th
birthday which is still a month ahead. So far I am still very well except
that I still have to spare my eyes and am not allowed to write by
gaslight. Let's hope I remain so.
Now I must close.
With warm regards,
Yours,
F. Engels